Pit Schultz on Wed, 16 Apr 1997 23:17:31 +0200 (MET DST) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> Constrained Constructivism by Katherine Hayles (2/2) |
The four positions are mapped onto a modified semiotic square as shown below. exclusion (inconsistent) False --------------- True (unoccupied) overlap (unknown) Not-True ---------------- Not-False (consistent) The horizontal relation between the two top positions, false and true, is constructed through a contrary relation that makes them mutually exclusive alternatives. What is true cannot be false, and what is false cannot be true. The bottom two positions, not-true and not-false, are in a more complex relation. Not-false, designated as the more restrictive, is occupied by models found to be consistent with the flux as it is interactively experienced. Not-true is occupied by models which have been imperfectly tested or not tested at all; these I call unknown. Between the negated categories of not-false and not-true, two kinds of oppositions are in play. One is a polarity between negation and affirmation (false/true), the other between indefinite and definite (unknown/consistent). This ambiguity folds together the ability to negate with the ability to specify. In doing so, it opens an escape hatch from the prison house of language. The entanglement of negation with specificity can be explored through the linguistic concepts of modality and marking. Traditionally defined, a modality is a statement containing a predicate that is affirmed or denied by other qualifications. The modern definition expands a modality into any statement about another statement. Non-modal articulations appear as mere statements of fact. In this sense they are unmarked, allowing for a reading that does not take the speaker's position into account. In general unmarked terms arethose which have been naturalized by cultural assumptions and so rendered transparent. "Man" is an unmarked noun, "woman" a marked one; "as old as" is an unmarked phrase, "as young as" a marked one. In modality the marking is accomplished by the qualifying phrase that calls attention to the statement's swerve from facticity. Affirmation and negation are non-modal; denial and assertion are modal. When the President's press secretary says, "The rumor is false [or true]," he has negated [or affirmed] it. When he says "I say that the rumor is false [or true]," he has denied [or asserted] it. Denial implies negation while subtly differing from it, just as assertion implies affirmation without exactly being affirmation. As their compound form signals, not-true and not-false are markedterms. Realism tends to elide the differences indicated by these markings, assimilating not-false into true and not-true into false.When a scientific textbook states "All the matter in the universe was once contracted to a very small area," the difference between the model and the reality tends to disappear, as do the position and processing of the observer for whom the statement makes sense. Far from eliding markings, the semiotic square displays them along the vertical axis. Expanding the binary dichotomy of realism to the quadrangle of semiotics, this distance-as-difference reminds us that articulations emerge from particular people speaking at specific times and places, with all of the species-specific processing and culturally-conditioned expectations that implies. The vertical axis thus separates as well as implicates, as shown in the schematic below. exclusion (inconsistent) False --------------- True (unoccupied) implication/separation overlap (unknown) Not-true -------------- Not-false (consistent) Beyond the marking that not-true and not-false share is the additional negativity inhering in not-true. Located at the lower left corner of the square, it occupies the space that on a Cartesian grid represents the negative of both axes. The negative of a negative, it is the position most resistant to assimilation into the transparencies of non-modal statements. Fredric Jameson calls it "the place of novelty and of paradoxical emergence," noting that it is "the most critical position and the one that remains open or empty for the longest time." (12) The implications of its excess negativity can be unpacked by again referring to modality. It is possible to negate a modality, creating as it were a double marking. The press secretary may say "I cannot say that the rumor is false [or true]," in which case the status of the rumor remains indeterminate. This situation corresponds to a residue within the not-true position that cannot be articulated--models that we cannot conceive because they are alien to our mode of processing the world. Not coincidentally, it also points to the reason why we cannot say a model is congruent with reality. Because we can never achieve a viewpoint outside our viewpoint, "unknown" overlaps with and implies "unknowable." Schleifer has argued that this kind of ambiguous negation is characteristic of scientific theories and art forms that elude either/or categorization, particularly quantum mechanics and literary modernism. (13) Shoshana Felman has called it "radical negativity," which "belongs neither to negation, nor to opposition, nor to correction . . . --it belongs precisely to scandal." (14) Calling this scandal the "outside of the alternative" because it emerges from a "negativity that is neither negative or positive" (p. 141-2), she suggests that it opens the way to reconceive referentiality (p. 76-77). In my terms, it allows the question of reference to be re-introduced without giving up the insights won by the new sociology of science when it bracketed reference. The relation of constraints to representation can now be articulated more precisely. When constraints become representations, they necessarily assume a positive cognitive content that moves them from the cusp into the theater. When I say "The total entropy of a closed system never decreases," I am expressing a representation of a constraint. Representations of this kind operate along the diagonal that connects inconsistent and consistent models. At the cusp, the interactions expressed by these representations have no positive content. The inability of language to specify these interactions as such is itself expressed by the elusive negativity that exists within the not-true position. The diagonal connecting true and not-true reveals their common concern with the limits of representation. At the positive ("true") end of the diagonal, the limits imply that we cannot speak the truth. At the negative ("not-true") end, they paradoxically perform the positive function of gesturing toward that which cannot be spoken. Elusive negativity, precisely because of its doubly negative position, opens onto the flux that cannot be represented initself. The complete semiotic square can now be given. exclusion (inconsistent) False ------------ True (unoccupied) implication/separation (unknown) Not-True ------------ Not-False (consistent) It is no accident that the semiotic constraints generating the semiotic square bring the not-true position into view. Language structures how we conceptualize any representation, including mathematical and scientific ones. But language is not all there is. Elusive negativity reveals a synergy between physical and semiotic constraints that brings language in touch with the world. Physical constraints, by their consistency, allude to a reality beyond themselves that they cannot speak; semiotic constraints, by generating excess negativity, encode this allusion into language. There is a correspondence between language and our world, but it is not the mysterious harmony Einstein posited when he said that the mystery of the universe is that it is understandable. Neither is it the self-reflexivity of a world created through language and nothing but language. Our interactions with the flux are always richer and more ambiguous than language can represent. Elusive negativity, acknowledging this gap, gestures toward this richness and so provides a place within semiotic systems to signify the unspeakable--to signify the cusp. IV. Making Connections: The Language of Metaphorics To posit a model for scientific inquiry is to presupposeor evoke a correlative view of language. A realistic model calls for and is reinforced by the assumption that language is a transparent medium transmitting ideas directly from one mind to another; a positivist model produces and is produced by attempts to formalize language into theory and observation components; a social constructivist model is associated with a non-referential view of language that sees discourse operating through relations of sameness and difference. These correspondences are not accidental. They must obtain in any coherent account of scientific inquiry, for inquiry is constituted as such only when it enters the social arena of discourse. Like other representations of scientific inquiry, constrained constructivism corresponds to a particular view of language. The view of language correlative with it can be found within the emerging field of metaphorics. The difference between a representation consistent with reality and one that depicts reality is the difference between a metaphor and a description. Constrained constructivism thus implies that all theories are metaphoric, just as all language is. Metaphorics, defined as the systematic study of metaphoric networks as constitutive of meaning production, presents a view of scientific inquiry that enriches and implies the figure of representation presented here. Since Max Black's influential analysis of metaphor, it has become customary to emphasize the power of metaphor to create new understanding. (15) According to this argument, metaphors not only express similarities between disparate concepts; they also set up complex currents of interaction that change how the terms brought into relation are understood. (16) A similar argument is adopted by Lakoff and Johnson in Metaphors We Live By. (17) Like Black, Lakoff and Johnson are concerned with systems of associated commonplaces that infuse into each other when two terms are brought into metaphoric interplay. Their emphasis falls on ordinary metaphors which, precisely because they do not surprise, reveal presuppositions deeply embedded within the culture. In Arbib and Hesse's The Construction of Reality, metaphorics is explicitly connected with scientific inquiry. (18) They argue that perception takes place through schema which operate through relational similarities and differences. The category "dog" has as its reference not some Platonic idea that captures the essence of dog, but a network of individual perceptions that form a group, albeit one fuzzy at the edges. In their account, the tension between similarity and difference characteristic of metaphor, farfrom being a special subset of language usage, is fundamental to how language works. The "loose bagginess" of the metaphoric relation allows for constantly changing configurations within metaphoric networks; these changes in turn correlate in a systematic fashion with shifts in paradigms. "Scientific revolutions," Arbib and Hesse write, "are, in fact, metaphoric revolutions, and theoretical explanation should be seen as metaphoric redescription of the domain of phenomena" (p. 156). In James J. Bono's account, metaphorics allows cultural presuppositions to be articulated together with scientific discourse systems. (19) Bono argues that metaphor functions "as both the site and means for exchanges among not only words or phrases, but also theories, frameworks, and most significantly, discourses" (p. 73). He envisions interactive, synchronic networks of metaphors that span disciplinary boundaries, in which traces of metaphors inherited diachronically from disciplinary traditions interfere and intersect with other metaphoric systems within the culture. Meaning production in this account can never be contained within a scientific field alone. Rather, it depends upon and emerges from resonances and interferences between inter- and extra-scientific networks of metaphors that engage one another at highly specific sites. Constrained constructivism matches these views of scientific language with an interactive, dynamic, locally situated model of representation. Recognizing that scientific theories operate within the theater of representation, it emphasizes that meaning production is socially and linguistically constructed. The elusive negativity that is a consequence of taking consistency rather than congruence as a standard for correctness reveals ambiguities intrinsic to any account of scientific models. These ambiguities ensure fluidity in language, thus reinforcing the claim that scientific revolutions are effected through metaphoric redescription. Finally, the transformative nature of interactions at the cusp makes the model context-dependent as well as species-specific, encouraging the idea that specific exchanges take place at local sites. Constrained constructivism thus presents a figure of representation that itself can be a metaphor for the inquiries of metaphorics. V. Situated Knowledge: No Outside But A Boundary Constrained constructivism puts limits on Derrida's aphorism that there is no outside to the text. Although there may be no outside that we can know, there is a boundary. The consequences that flow from positing a boundary or cusp rescue scientific inquiry from solipsism and radical subjectivism. At the same time, constrained constructivism acknowledges that we cannot have direct, unmediated access to reality. There is much to be said on why this acknowledgment is felt as an intolerable limitation by some realists. In "Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective," Donna Haraway alludes to the ideology embedded within an omniscient viewpoint when she calls t a "god trick." (20) Objectivity is associated with a view from everywhere, and hence from nowhere--a view with no limitations and hence no connections to humans located at specific places and times. (21) That it is a power trip is undeniable. That this power has frequently been misused is also undeniable. The illusion that one can achieve an omniscient vantage point, and the coercive practices associated with this illusion, have been so thoroughly deconstructed that they do not need further comment here. The liberatory spirit with which the critiques of objectivity were undertaken has been realized in the valuable contributions they have made to our understanding of how ideology and scientific objectivity mutually reinforce each other. But in the process, objectivity of any kind has gotten a bad name. I think this is a mistake, for the possibility of distinguishing a theory consistent with reality from one that is not can also be liberating. If there is no way to tell whether the claim that blacks and women have inferior brains is a less accurate account of reality than the claim that they do not, we have lost a valuable asset in the fight for liberation. George Levine eloquently made this point when he argued for the need to break out of coterie politics and strive for a faithful account of reality. (22) Donna Haraway also recognizes this possibility when she calls for a paradoxical, non-innocent stance that will recognize limited objectivity at the same time that it continues to deconstruct all claims to omniscient knowledge. The problem she wrestles with is underscored by Levine as the central issue of the contemporary sociology of knowledge: "how to have simultaneously an account of radical historical contingency for all knowledge claims and knowing subjects, a critical practice for recognizing our own 'semiotic technologies' for making meanings, and a no-nonsense commitment to faithful accounts of a 'real' world, one that can be partially shared and that is friendly to earthwide projects of finite freedom, adequate material abundance, modest meaning in suffering, and limited happiness" ("Situated Knowledges" p. 579). Haraway's solution is to emphasize that every perspective is partial, all knowledges situated. She tackles the difficult task she sets herself by continuing the vision metaphor but insisting that it is partial and contingent rather than full and unlimited. I am fully in sympathy with her project, and I think that she has articulated the central problem that a feminist sociology of knowledge faces. I am concerned, however, that the idea of partial vision can be easily misconstrued. It can be taken to suggest that part of our vision sees things as they really are, while only part is obscured. Whatever our vision is, this is not the case; we see things whole, not in parts. An alternative approach is to follow the lead of Merleau-Ponty when he suggests that situatedness, far from being a barrier to knowledge, enables it. (23) Given that we are not God, we can only come in touch with the universe through particular sets of sensory apparatus located within specific cultures and times. Constrained constructivism has this double edge: while it implies relativism, it also indicates an active construction of a reality that is meaningful to us through the dynamic interplay between us and the world. Renouncing omniscience and coercive power, it gains connectedness and human meaning. ---------------------------------------------------------------------------- Endnotes * In writing this essay, I have benefited from conversations and correspondence with F. C. McGrath, Ronald Schleifer, Walter Freeman, Evelyn Keller, and James Bono. George Levine and Gillian Beer gave helpful encouragement and guidance. 1. Donna Haraway, "Animal Sociology and a Natural Economyof the Body Politic, I and II," Signs 4 (1978): 21-60; Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air Pump: Hobbes,Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton: Princeton Univ, Press,1985); Bruno Latour, Science in Action: How to Follow ScientistsEngineers through Society (Milton Keynes: Open Univ. Press, 1987). 2. Michel Serres, Hermes: Literature, Science, Philosophy,ed. Josué V. Harari and David F. Bell (Baltimore: Johns HopkinsUniv. Press, 1982) 106. 3. "What the Frog's Eye Tells the Frog's Brain," J. Y. Lettvin,H. R. Maturana, W. S. McCulloch, and W. H. Pitts, Proceedings of the Institute for Radio Engineers, 47 (1959): 1940-51. 4. For a summary of visual mechanisms in different species, see Models of the Visual Cortex, eds. David Rose and Vernon G. Dobson (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1985). 5. Christine A. Skarda, "Understanding Perception: Self-Organizing Neural Dynamics," La Nuova Critica 9-10 (1989): 49-60. See also Walter Freeman and Christine Skarda, "Mind/Body Science: Neuroscience on Philosophy of Mind," John Searle and His Critics,eds. E. LePore and R. van Gulick (London: Blackwell, 1988);and "Representations: Who Needs Them?" Proceedings 3rd Conference on the Neurobiology of Learning and Memory (forthcoming). 6. Walter Freeman, private communication. 7. Jacques Derrida, Dissemination, trans. Barbara Johnson Chicago: Chicago Univ. Press, 1981). 8. Evelyn Fox Keller, Reflections on Gender and Science (New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1985); Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers, Order Out of Chaos: Man's New Dialogue with Nature (New York: Bantam, 1984); Nancy Cartwright, How the Laws of Physics Lie (New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1983); and Michel Serres, Hermes (1982). 9. A. J. Greimas, "The Interaction of Semiotic Constraints," On Meaning: Selected Writings in Semiotic Theory, trans. Paul J. Perron and Frank H. Collins (Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1987) 48-62. 10. Ronald Schleifer, A. J. Greimas and the Nature of Meaning:Linguistics, Semiotics and Discourse Theory (London: Croom Helm,1987) 22-55. 11. Karl L. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growthof Scientific Knowledge, 2nd ed. (New York: Basic Books, 1965). 12. Fredric Jameson, "Foreword," On Meaning (xvi). 13. Ronald Schleifer, "Analogy and Example: Heisenberg, Negation, and the Language of Quantum Mechanics,". ms. See also Ronald Schleifer, Rhetoric and Death: The Language of Modernism and Postmodern Discourse Theory (Champaign: Univ. of Illinois Press, 1990). 14. Shoshana Felman, The Literary Speech Act: Don Juan with J. L. Austin, or Seduction in Two Languages, trans. Catherine Porter (Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1983) 141-2. 15. Max Black, Models and Metaphors (Ithaca: Cornell Univ.Press, 1962). See also "More About Metaphor," Metaphor and Thought, ed. Andrew Ortony (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1979) 19-43. 16. Paul Ricoeur emphasizes the torque that metaphors put on terms in Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth: Texas Christian Univ. Press, 1976). 17. George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1980). 18. Michael A. Arbib and Mary B. Hesse, The Construction of Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1986) 147-70. 19. James J. Bono, "Science, Discourse, and Literature: The Role/Rule of Metaphor in Science," Literature and Science: Theory and Practice, ed. Stuart Peterfreund (Boston: Northeastern Univ. Press, 1990) 59-89. 20. Donna Haraway, "Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism as a Site of Discourse on the Privilege of Partial Perspective," Feminist Studies 14 (1988): 575-99. 21. For a different (and more realist) position on how subjectivity and objectivity can be integrated, see Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986). 22. George Levine, Plenary Address at the Society for Literature and Science Society Conference, September 1988. 23. Merleau-Ponty, The Phenomenology of Perception (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1962). ---------------------------------------------------------------------------- N. Katherine Hayles Department of English University of California 405 Hilgard Avenue Los Angeles CA 90024-12530 e- mail: Hayles@humnet.ucla.edu Current Research: Virtual Bodies: Evolving Materiality in Cybernetics, Literature, and Information. Book-length manuscript tracing history of cybernetics from 1945-present and relating it to poststructural critical theory and Riding the Cusp: The Interplay between Narrative and Formalisms, under contract to Routledge Press. An essay collection focused on showing the importance of narrative in a series of scientific sites, from game theory to sociobiology and artificial life. --- # distributed via nettime-l : no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a closed moderated mailinglist for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@icf.de and "info nettime" in the msg body # URL: http://www.desk.nl/~nettime/ contact: nettime-owner@icf.de