Pit Schultz on Wed, 16 Apr 1997 23:08:44 +0200 (MET DST) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> Constrained Constructivism by Katherine Hayles (1/2) |
[this is one of a long series of textes within the nettime flow, one could call 'neo-classics'. Luckily you find some of them on the net already, others have to get scanned from paper. These are textes which have the status of little milestones or manifestos and which are already payed for, so it is easy to get permission within a non- commercial context of fair use. Such texts are often quoted and linked, forming redundant trails and patterns of the fundament of what we call 'net critique'. A collection of those textes under the publishing right of fair and noncommerical use is one of the many possible tasks of a pragmatic theory of a 'Free Content Coalition'. Join us! -- the following text is adding to the representation thread, i hope it helps smooth out a certain common tendency to millenial paranoia and numb confusion, maybe amplified by the ongoing changes onto the semiotic planes of 'culture'. it's often easier to filter/post such constructive textes then writing an own essay but it can have the same effects. -p] http://englishwww.humnet.ucla.edu/Individuals/Hayles/Cusp.html N. Catherine Hayles Constrained Constructivism : Locating Scientific Inquiry in the Theater of Representation I. The Theater of Representation* One of the important developments in science studies has been the increased awareness that scientific inquiries are social and ideological constructions. Donna Haraway's explorations of primatology, Shapin and Schaffer's investigations into the sociology of Boyle's laboratory, and Bruno Latour's study of "black boxes" in science are only a few of the seminal analyses that have challenged accounts of how science is done (1). So extensive and successful have these critiques been that it now seems the aspect of science most in need of explanation is its power to arrive at apparently ahistorical and transcultural generalizations. Given that science is socially constructed, how can we explain, as Michel Serres puts it, that "entropy increases in a closed system, regardless of the latitude and whatever the ruling class." (2) A clue can be found in a curious lacuna that occurs when this question is discussed within the philosophy of science. There the debate has been constructed as a division between the realists and the anti-realists. Both sides grant that there is something called observables, and that these observables have an instrumental efficacy in the world. You tighten a loose battery cable, and the car starts where it would not before. The difference comes in whether or not the observables relate to entities that exist in reality as such. The realists say there really is an electrical current that flows, while the anti-realists want to weaken or deny this claim. The lacuna occurs in the anthropomorphic grounding that underlies the idea of observables. Without being explicit about it, both sides mean observable from a human perspective. This assumption has important implications. Consider a frog's visual cortex. Studies indicate that objects at rest elict little or no neural response in a frog's brain. (3) Maximum response is elicted by small objects in rapid, erratic motion--say, a fly buzzing by. Large objects evoke a qualitatively different response than small ones. This arrangement makes sense from a frog's perspective, because it allows the frog to identity prey from non-prey, and prey from predators that want to eat it. Now imagine that a frog is presented with Newton's laws of motion. The first law, you recall, says that an object at rest remains so unless acted upon by a force. Encoded into the formulation is theassumption that the object stays the same; the new element is the force. This presupposition, so obvious from a human point of view, would be almost unthinkable from a frog's perspective, since for the frog moving objects are processed in an entirely different way than stationary ones. Newton's first law further states, as a corollary, that an object moving in a straight line continues to move so unless compelled to change by forces acting upon it. The proposition would certainly not follow as a corollary for the frog, for variation of motion rather than continuation counts in his perceptual scheme. Moreover, it ignores the size of the object, which from a frog's point of view is crucial to how information about movement is processed. My point is not that humans know what frogs cannot fathom. The scientists who did the frog research put it well: their work "shows that the [frog's] eye speaks to the brain in a language already highly organized and interpreted instead of transmitting some more or less accurate copy of the distribution of light upon the receptors" (Lettvin et al., 1950). This and other studies conclusively demonstrate that there can be no perception without a perceiver.(4) Our so-called observables are permeated at every level by assumptions located specifically in how humans process information from their environments. Observing with instruments rather than unaided human perception does not rescue us from our anthropomorphism, for the instruments we design and build are just those that would be conceptualized by someone with our sensory equipment. Instruments extend and refine human perceptions, but they do not escape the assumptions encoded within the human sensorium. Add the profound influence of acculturation upon cognitive processing, and it becomes clear that observables really mean observations made by humans located at specific times and places and living in specific cultures. In short, we are always already within the theater of representation. Everything we perceive, think, or do is always already a representation, not reality as such. Yet representation may be too passive a concept to account for the complexities involved. Research by Walter Freeman and Christine Skarda on the olfactory bulb of rabbits indicates that perceptual processing is context-dependent as well as species-specific.(5) Rabbits continually sniff; these sniffs take in molecules of odorants that fall on the cilia of receptor cells in the nose, which in turn are connected to mitral cells in the olfactory bulb of the cortex. When the odors are neutral, oscillatory bursts of neural activity appear that can be reliably identified as characteristic of a given animal. When the animal sniffs an odor that he has been conditioned to recognize as significant, a different pattern appears. Then the burst is amplified in a cascading effect that brings together selectively co-activated neurons in a nerve cell assembly. This amplification happens very fast, within milliseconds. At certain critical thresholds, further changes take place that affect the entire global area of the olfactory bulb. The data demonstrate that perception is not a passive response to stimuli but an active process of self-organization that depends on prior learning and specific contexts. "Perception begins within the organism with internally generated neural activity," Skarda writes (p. 52). "What happens within the brain is about interaction" (p. 53). Although the data vary with individual animals and between species, additional experiments on the visual cortex of the monkey and the somatosensory cortex of a human subject indicate that the active, self-organizing nature of perception applies in these cases as well.(6) On this basis, Skarda and Freeman have argued that neuroscience should give up the concept of representation (which Skarda calls "representationalism"), because it encourages the fallacy that perception passively mirrors the external world. Representation in this sense happens only when an observer enters the scene. It is the experimenter's viewpoint, Skarda writes, which "requires that conclusions be drawn about what the observed activity patterns represent to the subject" (p. 57). From this vantage,our anthropomorphism has not only led us to universalize our species-specific perspective into a vision of an autonomously existing reality but also to falsify the nature of our own perceptual processing. The point is telling. I am not willing, however, to relinquish a term as central to literary discourse as representation. I want to introduce another way of formulating it that will make representation a dynamic process rather than a static mirroring. Suppose we think about the reality "out there" as an unmediated flux. The term emphasizes that it does not exist in any of the usual conceptual terms we might construct (such as reality, the universe, the world, etc.) until it is processed by an observer. It interacts with and comes into consciousness through self-organizing, transformative processes that include sensory and cognitive components. These processes I will call the cusp. On one side of the cusp is the flux, inherently unknowable and unreachable by any sentient being. On the other side are the constructed concepts that for us comprise the world. Thinking only about the outside of the cusp leads to the impression that we can access reality directly and formulate its workings through abstract laws that are universally true. Thinking only about the inside leads to solipsism and radical subjectivism. The hardest thing in the world is to ride the cusp, to keep in the foreground of consciousness both the active transformations through which we experience the world and the flux that interacts with and helps to shape those transformations. For as soon as the thought forms, we become aware of the paradox: what we imagine is not the cusp itself, but the representation of it that is in our conceptual realm. The reflexive mirroring that enfolds cusp into concept shows how we can be trapped within the prison house of language. This inherent reflexivity was part of what Derrida had in mind when he famously proclaimed "There is no outside to the text."(7) As long as positive assertions are made, there is indeed no way out of the reflexive loop, no way to conceptualize the cusp without always already falling short of what the conceptualization attempts to represent. Negation, however, is a more complex and ambiguous function. In negation, possibilities for articulation exist that can elude the reflexive mirroring that would encapsulate us within textuality and nothing but textuality. This elusive negativity authorizes a position that grants the full weight of the constructivist argument but draws back from saying anything goes. Such a position is necessary if science is to retain its distinctive characteristic as an inquiry into the nature of the physical world, while also rightfully being recognized as an arena of social discourse and cultural practice. Central to it are contexts, consistency, and constraints. Their interaction allows the cusp to be posited and its relation to elusive negativity explored. II. Riding the Cusp: What We Remember, What We Forget This afternoon Hunter and I went for a walk. Hunter is a handsome, medium-sized dog, half beagle and half hound. Hunting rabbits is bred into his genes, and there are a lot of rabbits where we live. It is not uncommon for a rabbit to run across the road in front of us. He sees it, I see that he sees it, he sees that I see he sees it. Having lived with Hunter for over ten years, I know that I have about two seconds to convince him to remain at heel rather than run after the rabbit. I also know that the outcome will depend in part on how authoritative my voice is, how close the rabbit, how intense the scent and how bad his arthritis. Most of the time I succeed in convincing him not to run; occasionally I fail. In either case, complex communications take place between us about an external reality that we both perceive and that affects our actions. How does this happen? No doubt Hunter processes the world in a very different way than I do, from the limited color range he experiences to the vastly richer role scent plays in his universe. Despite these differences, we are able to communicate because we share a context that remains largely consistent from day to day. I do not perceive the world as he does, but my perception of his perception stays relatively constant. I know the kinds of things that excite his attention and what his probable responses will be, just as he knows mine. When the rabbit runs across our path, we each react within our different sensory realms to a stimulus that catalyzes our responses, which are also conditioned by past experiences with the world and each other. This consistency allows for the shorthand "Hunter sees the rabbit," although on reflection I am aware that "rabbit" is an anthropomorphic concept that Hunter does not share with me in anything like the same sense another human being could. The unmediated flux impinges on him, impinges on me; I see the rabbit and Hunter's response in my way, he sees the rabbit and my response in his. We both know that we are responding to an event we hold in common, as well as to a context that includes memories of similar events we have shared. The temptation to forget the complexities of this account and abstract to the shorthand is very strong. From such abstraction comes the belief that nature operates according to laws that are universally and impartially true. What is the harm in moving tothe abstraction? The implications become clear when we look at what it leaves out of account. Gone from view are the species-specific position and processing of the observer; the context that conditions observation, even before conscious thought forms; and the dynamic, interactive nature of the encounter. In such a pared-down account, it is easy to believe that reality is static and directly accessible, chance and unpredictability are aberrations, and interaction is nothing more than an additive combination of individual factors, each of which can be articulated and analyzed separate from the others. This is, of course, the world of classical physics. It continues to have a vigorous existence in popular culture as well as in the presuppositions of many practicing scientists. When the TV camera, accompanied by Carl Sagen's voice-over, zooms through the galaxy to explore the latest advances in cosmology, these presuppositions are visually and verbally encoded into an implied viewpoint that seems to be unfettered by limitations of context and free from any particular mode of sensory processing. As a representation, this simulacrum figures representation itself as an inert mirroring of a timeless, objective reality. Perhaps its most pernicious aspect is the implicit denial of itself as a representation. The denial is all the more troubling because of the ideological implications encoded within it. Among those who have explored these implications are Evelyn Fox Keller, who points out the relation between an "objective" attitude, the masculine orientation of science, and the construction of the world as an object for domination and control; Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stenger, who relate the appeal of a timeless realm to a fear of emotional involvement and death; Nancy Cartwright, who demonstrates that the idea of scientific "laws" always derives from the act of analysis and never intrinsically from the situation itself; and Michel Serres, who reminds us that deviations from idealized, abstract forms are not exceptions but the noise that constitutes the world.(8) These critiques can be seen as acts of recovery, attempts to excavate from an abstracted shorthand the complexities that unite subject and object in a dynamic, interactive, on-going process of perception and social construction. A model of representation that declines the leap to abstraction figures itself as species-specific, culturally determined, and context-dependent. Emphasizing instrumental efficacy rather than precision, it assumes local interactions rather than positive correspondences that hold universally. It engages in a rhetoric of "good enough," indexing its conclusions to the context in which implied judgments about adequacy are made. Yet it also recognizes that within the domains specified by these parameters, enough consistencies obtain in the processing and in the flux to make recognition reliable and relatively stable. Since the claim for consistency separates this position from strict social construction, it is worth exploring more fully. Central to this claim is the idea of constraints. By ruling out some possibilities--by negating articulations--constraints enable scientific inquiry to tell us something about reality and not only about ourselves. Consider how conceptions of gravity have changed over the last three hundred years. In the Newtonian paradigm, gravity is conceived very differently than in the general theory of relativity. For Newton, gravity resulted from the mutual attraction between masses; for Einstein, from the curvature of space. One might imagine still other kinds of explanations, for example a Native American belief that objects fall to earth because the spirit of Mother Earth calls out to kindred spirits in other bodies. No matter how gravity is conceived, no viable model could predict that when someone steps off a cliff on earth, she will remain spontaneously suspended in mid-air. This possibility is ruled out by the nature of physical reality. Although the constraints that lead to this result are interpreted differently in different paradigms, they operate universally to eliminate certain configurations from the range of possible answers. Gravity, like any other concept, is always and inevitably a representation. Yet within the representations we construct, some are ruled out by constraints, others are not. The power of constraints to enable these distinctions depends upon a certain invariability in their operation. For example, the present limit on silicon technology is a function of how fast electrons move through the semiconductor. One could argue that "electron" is a social construction, as are "semiconductor" and "silicon." Nevertheless, there is an unavoidable limit inherent in this constraint, and it will manifest itself in whatever representation is used, provided it is relevant to the representational construct. Suppose that the first atomic theories had developed using the concept of waves rather than particles. Then we would probably talk not about electrons and semiconductors, but indices of resistance and patterns of refraction. There would still be a limit, however, on how fast messages could be conveyed using silicon materials. If both sets of representations were available, one could demonstrate that the limit expressed through one representation is isomorphic with the limit expressed in the other. Note that I am not saying constraints tell us what reality is. This they cannot do. But they can tell us which representations are consistent with reality, and which are not. By enabling this distinction, constraints play an extremely significant role in scientific research, especially when the representations presented for disconfirmation are constrained so strongly that only one is possible. The art of scientific experimentation consists largely of arranging situations so the relevant constraints operate in this fashion. No doubt there are always other representations, unknown and perhaps for us unimaginable, that are also consistent with reality. The representations we present for falsification are limited by what we can imagine, which is to say, by the prevailing modes of representation within our culture, history, and species. But within this range, constraints can operate to select some as consistent with reality, others as not. We cannot see reality in its positivity. We can only feel it through isomorphic constraints operating upon competing local representations. The term I propose for the position I have been urging is constrained constructivism. The positive identities of our concepts derive from representation, which gives them form and content. Constraints delineate ranges of possibility within which representations are viable. Constrained constructivism points to the interplay between representation and constraints. Neither cut free from reality not existing independent of human perception, the world as constrained constructivism sees it is the result of active and complex engagements between reality and human beings. Constrained constructivism invites--indeed cries out for--cultural readings of science, since the representations presented for disconfirmation have everything to do with prevailing cultural and disciplinary assumptions. At the same time, not all representations will be viable. It is possible to distinguish between them on the basis of what is really there. Are constraints not themselves representations? If so, how is the claim for their invariability justified? With thesequestions, the distance between articulation and cusp threatens to collapse, cutting off the connections that interactively put us in touch with the unmediated flux. To answer them and elaborate the dynamic figure of representation, I return to the crucial difference between congruence and consistency. Congruence implies one-to-one correspondence. In Euclidean geometry, one can test for congruence by putting one triangle on top of another and seeing whether they match. If the area and shape of one exactly fits the other, congruence is achieved; any deviation indicates that they are not congruent. Congruency thus falls within the binary logic of true/false. Consistency, by contrast, cannot adequately be accounted for in a two-valued logic. In addition to true and false, two other positions--let us call them not-true and not-false--are necessary. The introduction of these two values reveals an important asymmetry between affirmation and negation. From this asymmetry emerges a sense of the relation between language and representation that steps outside the reductive dichotomies of the realist/anti-realist debate. III. The Semiotic Square and Elusive Negativity Mapping the four positions mentioned above onto a semiotic square will make explicit the multiple connections and disjunctions that constitute their interactions. A. J. Greimas introduced the semiotic square as a way to represent the possibilities for signification in any semiotic system.(9) These possibilities, although very rich, are not infinite. They are created through the interaction of what Greimas called "semiotic constraints"--deep structures that enable meaning to emerge by restricting articulations to certain axes of signification. Ronald Schleifer has interpreted and expanded on Greimas's construction of the semiotic square, and the discussion that follows is indebted to his work as well as to Greimas. (10 ) If we grant that we are always already within the theater of representation, it follows that no unambiguous or necessary connection can be forged between reality and our representations. Whatever the unmediated flux is, it remains unknowable by the finite subject. Representations arise in response to such historically specific factors as prevailing disciplinary paradigms and cultural assumptions, as well as such species-specific factors as the human sensorium and neurophysiology. Observations are culturally conditioned and anthropomorphically determined. We can never know how our representations coincide with the flux, for we can never achieve a standpoint outside them. Consequently, the true position cannot be occupied because we cannot verify congruence. The false position, however, can be occupied. Within the range of representations available at a given time we can ask, "Is this representation consistent with the aspects of reality under interrogation?" If the answer is affirmative, we still know only our representations, not the flux itself. But if it is negative, we know that the representation does not adequately account for our interaction with the flux in a way that is meaningful to us in that context. The asymmetry revealed by this analysis should not be confused with Popper's doctrine of falsification. (11) Understanding that theories could not be verified, Popper nevertheless maintained congruence as a conceptual possibility. The problem for him was that congruence was empirically based and so always liable to exceptions that might appear in the future. In the scheme articulated here, future exceptions do not play a privileged role in explaining why congruence cannot be achieved. Even if by some fiat we could be sure that no future exceptions would exist, the most we could say is that a model is consistent with reality as it is experienced by someone with our sensory equipment and previous contextual experience. Congruence cannot be achieved because it implies perception without a perceiver. --- # distributed via nettime-l : no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a closed moderated mailinglist for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@icf.de and "info nettime" in the msg body # URL: http://www.desk.nl/~nettime/ contact: nettime-owner@icf.de