McKenzie Wark on Fri, 26 Feb 1999 18:43:34 +0100 (CET) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> Celebrities, Culture and Cyberspace |
extract 005 Celebrities, Culture and Cyberspace, by McKenzie Wark http://www.mcs.mq.edu.au/~mwark Here's one more extract. The book is now available from Pluto PressAustralia http://socialchange.net.au/pluto/ Postindustrial Class Struggle McKenzie Wark If there is a reason why the left often appears to be struggling to keep up with the pace of change, it may be that the forces traditionally identified as 'left' no longer represent the frontline in the class conflict that, in Marxist thinking, determines the forward movement of history. Much of the agenda of the left seems either to be about resisting change completely or accommodating to it in ways that preserve the interests of certain constituencies, particularly those skilled workers in manufacturing and in the white collar public sector that belong to left wing unions.Barry Jones identified an information proletariat, but he did not claim to have thought through the postindustrial society in terms of class conflict. ! His prophecy was that "the question of control of, and access to, information should become one of the major political issues of the 1990s", but he did not pose this question in class terms. Information may work as differently in the market economy as capital does to rent, and might therefore generate quite different kinds of class interest. I want to conclude this chapter with some highly speculative remarks that try, in a very abstract way, to advance the conceptualisation of the conjuncture of the late 90s. This last section is addressed to a certain kind of culture of the left. Those not so inclined might find the next chapter, which deals with Labor's culture of the right, more congenial."Rent is that portion of the produce of the earth that is paid to the landlord for the use of the original and indestructible powers of the soil. It is often, however, confounded with the interest and profit of capital...".1 So wrote David Ricardo, one of the original 'economic rationalists', in what was one of the first, although certainly not the last attempt to define the difference between rent and profit, the returns respectively on land and capital.Land is of fixed quantity. There is only so much of it. Any economic activity based on land behaves in much the same peculiar way. When demand rises, prices rise, but if there is no more land to meet the demand for what land produces, then the high price does not encourage new competitors Ñ by definition there can be no new competitors, as the quantity of land is fixed. If there were new competitors, they would add to supply, supply would match the new high level of demand, and prices would trend down again. But there is no more land, no new competitors, so as demand rises, prices shoot up, and owners of land collect a rent derived from possession of this fixed asset. In principle, a mine, an office block and a prime piece of farm land behave in much the same way in the marketplace. Most things are not o! f fixed quantity, and don't offer an opportunity to extract rent. If a factory makes widgets, or a company offers a service, and demand for those widgets or that service rises, competitors can come into the market attracted by the high prices. These new competitors add to supply and drive down the price. This is where the more strictly capitalist economy thrives, by investing in bringing to market products or services that can be sold for more than the investment, and hence return a profit. Unlike rents, profits are not protected by the fixed quantity of the inputs. Of course, many capitalists would like their business to accrue rents rather than profits, and governments are often dragged in to the creation of artificial rent-producing monopolies in anything from steel to television. People who own land or capital hire people who have neither to work for them. Owners have an interest in keeping down the wages they pay, whereas workers have an interest in driving them up. Thi! s conflict of interest may not be a complete one, however. In the modern world, workers require security and stability of employment, and come to have a shared interest with their employer in the maintenance of those conditions. Higher wages might be good in the short run, but not if this shuts off profits, sends the company broke, and tosses the worker out of a job. Owners and workers may have different interests, but their interests are not simply opposed to each other, unless you accept the fable that by overthrowing the owners, the workers will inherit the earth. There is one significant difference between working for someone who owns land and someone who owns capital. When demand for land or what land produces is high, it's possible for the wage earner to make demands for much higher wages without sending the owner of land broke. The owner of land is much more likely to just pass the increased cost on to the purchaser. After all, new competitors can't come in to bankrupt the rentier, and hence the job of the worker is more secure. This is why mining and building workers were, until recently, more able to extract wage increases out of owners of land than other workers were out of owners of capital. Demanding higher wages was unlikely to send the company broke. Actually, under a high tariff system, the whole economy can work more like a rent economy than a capital economy. Protectionism creates quasi-rent conditions for lots of businesses, and lots of workers can demand wage rises that just get passed on to the purchaser. There are already two kinds of economy in this classical conceptualisation of how it all works. But what if we add a third kind of economy Ñ the information economy? Actually, before Adam Smith or David Richardo got around to theorising rent and capital, the new information economy was already becoming a reality. When English law recognises the rights of authors and engravers to 'own' the content of their works, the conce! pt of property was in principle extended to information. Before then, any printer could copy any book Ñ ownership resided in the thing, the book itself, not the ordering of the information within it. With copyright a reality, a new kind of property owner arises Ñ the owner of copyright. Not coincidentally, a new kind of celebrity, and anew kind of urbanity arises at the same time as the recognition of this new kind of property. Samuel Johnson was one of the first writers to openly make his living from his trade, and became famous for it. Johnson claimed that "there seems to be in authors a stronger right of property than that by occupancy; a metaphysical right, a right, as it were, of creation...".2 Johnson realised that this property right had to be balanced against the common interest in that the knowledge contained in a book be "universally diffused among mankind." Hence Johnson argued for an exclusive right that would be limited in duration. As Mark Rose of the Univers! ity of California argues, "at one level, the literary-property question was a legal struggle about the nature of property and how the law might adapt itself to the changed circumstances of an economy based on trade. At another, it was a contest about how far the ideology of possessive individualism should be extended into the realm of cultural production."3As it turned out, it could be extended very far indeed. As with the ownership of land or capital, the arguments made for it could be based on the doctrines of natural law. Someone is entitled to own whatever is the object and product of their own labour. But the creation of information as a form of private and tradeable property is no more natural than the creation of land and capital as private property. A fully market-based economy rests on the convention of property, backed by the authority of the courts. Information can be an object of a law of property, just like capital or land, but does not necessarily behave the ! same way. What is distinctive about information is firstly that my possession of it need not deprive you of it. I cannot possess land that you at the same time possess, but I can know something that you at the same time know. The possession of information does not require the dispossession of another. Secondly, copying information is distinct form creating it. If I grow wheat or make a shoe, the copying of either of these things takes as much effort as making them, and is in fact an identical act to making them. If I write a book or compose a song, the copying of it requires much less effort. An effort tending, from the invention of moveable type to the invention of the floppy disc, to diminish to nothing. In short, information behaves very differently to a physical thing, and as a form of property it is quite the opposite of land. Land cannot be copied and is in fixed supply; information can be endlessly copied, and the copying of it is simple compared to making it in the fir! st place. The principles of the information economy have existed for hundreds of years, and were worked out alongside the legal fictions for other kinds of property according to which a commodity economy would be regulated. It is late in the 20th century that the information economy has become conspicuous in size and influence, in part because the evolution of the technical means of storing and distributing information have advanced very rapidly. Most information workers, like most agricultural and industrial workers, have to sell their capacity to work, and do not, in the end, own what they make. The worker might have the capacity in their head or hands to produce something, but lack the means to realise it. Where other workers confront owners of land or capital, information workers confront owners of what I call vectors. A vector is the physical and technical means of moving information across space, or preserving it across time. As with agriculture or industry, the tech! nical development of information reaches a point where economies of scale dictate the formation of large enterprises which own and control vast vectors for the distribution of information, just as other businesses control vast tracts of land or physical plant and equipment. What is often conceived as globalisation may just be the growth of the information economy due to the technical advance of the vector, and the subordination of the economies of capital and land to it. The reason for this is not hard to fathom. The functioning of markets presupposes the transmission of information labour demand, supply and the prices that mediate between from one place to another. The information economy grows, in part, on its capacity to expand the opportunities for owners of land and capital. What is often perceived as a shift in the balance of power from labour to capital in the 90s may rather be a shift in the centre of gravity of economic activity, from the economies of capital and ! land, to that of information. The most conspicuous beneficiaries of such a shift are the owners of vectors, the Murdochs and Packers. Less noticed are those beneficiaries who are not owners but merely workers in this expanding economy, which includes both information-specific businesses, and also the information component of the business of capital and land, of making things and growing things.What appears as an information proletariat is a pool of unemployed or marginally employed people who have not made the transition from an economy dominated by making things to an economy dominated by making information. Just as the transition from agriculture to manufacturing produced an under-employed population, this second transition also produces such a proletariat, and once again, in its desperation, it is tempted to embrace populist solutions, involving a strong state that will maintain an economy to its liking. The left has always been an unstable and uneasy alliance, and has ! always included the representatives of industrial labour, the most organised part of the economy of capital and the making and things. It has also included members of the information-working class. The difficulty for the left is that the interests of these different kinds of worker are further apart than ever. The former are tempted to struggle for the retarding of the shift in the centre of gravity toward the information economy. The latter have no interest in such a retrogressive step, and have their own agenda of conflicts over the conditions under which they sell the information they produce to the owners of media vectors. The information economy is at the same time an information culture. As Mark Rose argues, the extension of "possessive individualism" into culture via the legal fiction that information can be private property is an old principle. It just became more obvious, late in the 20th century, what this commodification of information has all along implied: cultu! re and economy are inseparable. There was always a market for information upon which the culture of everyday life depended. What changed is the development of new vectors, such as radio, television and the internet, which could be accumulated and co-ordinated, as elements of a powerful kind of market economy. As a consequence, politics, no less than the economy, became saturated by vectors. The vectoral becomes the space of political action no less than of economic gain. The creation of political majorities becomes a matter of articulating popular desires via media images. This process has been advancing for some time, overcoming the social and communal basis of political affiliation. Politics in the information age is about the formation of majorities that are synchronised around particular images.Majorities may be articulated on the basis of a shared desire for something, or against it. Both the left and the right have a history of the articulation of desire against thin! gs. The right depended on the articulation of desire in the form of hatred of communism throughout the cold war Ñ a tactic that contributed to the weakening of the right when the Berlin wall came down. In this they merely succeeded where the left failed, in its attempt to turn the difference between the interests of workers and owners into an opposition that would pit workers against ownership in general Ñ the class war. Both the left and the right must share some culpability for the rise of a populism that has no qualms about identifying the most vulnerable minorities as the object of a majoritarian hatred. Populism exploits the pleasure machine of desire, as it works in the vectoral world, and can achieve substantial gains. The irony is that populism achieves its gains using the cultural machinery of information precisely because of discontent with the effects of the power of information to undermine the economic position of what now becomes an information proletariat.Po! litics as desire for something, rather than desire which attempts to opposed a majority to a minority, faces the added difficulty that the articulation of mass desire must occur in public. Desire compounds desire, but also fragments, dissipates, comes in conflict with itself. If there is a majoritarian politics to be created, it might not be the politics of consensus, which presupposes community of interest, not just between capital and labour, but also between the economies of cultivating land, manufacturing things and processing information. It might be a politics of connection rather than consensus, of articulating connections rather than a corporatism rooted in the old manufacturing economy. The politics of consensus assume a mass media that works rather like mass manufacturing. It composes its majority on the basis of blocks of shared interest that can be articulated in a few broad strokes in a mass media vector. The politics of connection, on the other hand, might be m! ore appropriate for a world in which diverse vectors proliferate, and the interests that have to be composed to form a majority are not based firmly in a mass manufacturing economy, but span two different kinds of economy, that of the manufacture of things and the production of information. In short, a 'political economy' of the age of information has to take account of what is specific to the information economy. Like land, information deviates from some key assumptions about the commodity economy of things. The commodification of culture has always been a part of the development of the information economy, no matter how much of a recent phenomena this may appear. It is implied in the original formulation of the legal fiction of information as property. A certain kind of celebrity, as someone who in a sense owns an image and story of which they are the producer, is a byproduct of this commodification. It too is not new, and in someone like Samuel Johnson there is a prototyp! e for contemporary celebrity. Celebrity, in turn, is a concept that can hold together the economic and political aspects of this 'political economy' of information. The appearance of celebrity is not just an artefact of the commodification of culture, but also of the immersion of politics within the relations of the vector. These are not ephemeral additions to the commodity economy, they are aspects of it that have been developing for some time. The creation of a form of property for information has just been waiting for the technical development of the vectors of information relations to release the potential latent in it. This is just a rough sketch, starting with Barry Jones' insight into the existence of an information proletariat, and speculating on what larger picture it may fit into. It is somewhat removed from rather pragmatic approach of, say, Lindsay Tanner. But perhaps what Tanner's insights into the changing options for the left of the Labor Party needs is some! larger framework within which to plot the changes, rather than reacting on the basis of out-dated maps of how the commodity economy functions. In any case, the left no longer have a monopoly on conceptual thinking in the Labor Party and the labour movement, and perhaps it never did. As I want to show in the next, and last, chapter, the light on the hill can also be regenerated in terms quite outside those of the left. ***McKenzie Wark's Celebrities, Culture and Cyberspace is available fromPluto Press Australia http://socialchange.net.au/pluto/ 1 David Ricardo, On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, Cambridge University Press, 1952, p. 67 2 James Boswell, Life of Johnson, Oxford University Press, 1964, vol. 2, p. 259 3 Mark Rose, Authors and Owners: The Invention of Copyright, Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass., 1993, p. 92 --- # distributed via nettime-l : no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a closed moderated mailinglist for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@desk.nl and "info nettime-l" in the msg body # URL: http://www.desk.nl/~nettime/ contact: nettime-owner@desk.nl