Cubitt Sean on 4 Jul 2000 15:26:18 -0000 |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> Virilio and ecology: transoport, transmit, translate |
Transport, Transmit, Translate Virilio, Ecology and the Media Sean Cubitt Paper Given at the Crossroads in Cultural Studies Conference, University of Birmingham, 23 June 2000 Don't drink and drive: take speed and run (Anon) There is not and never has been a primordial experience which can serve as ground for a phenomenological account of sociality. In Virilio, the media, mediation in general, appear always as secondary, always standing after the primordial experience of the face to face, of labour, of perception or whatever else is premised as defining of humanity. This residual humanism leads to some other problems in Virilio's otherwise valuable account of the contemporary mediascape. This paper is an attempt to redraw some of Virilio's arguments in the interests of an ecological aesthetics. In my generation, and certainly in younger ones, the mediated inhabits even the primal universe of the infant. I think we got a television when I was about ten, but the radio and the record player, and most of all books, especially atlases but also story books and the habit of reading, permeated my infant years alongside days spent mucking about in the farmyards and fields, playing with the animals or scrumping apples. I remember how vivid was the presence to me in the late 1950s of the Second World War and even of the Irish War of Independence and the subsequent Civil War. They were as real as my guardian angel and the seven sacraments. As real as the priest, the school teacher and my father. Like any childhood, mine hangs slightly to one side of history, a time frozen in memory, a landscape, as Virilio has it, of events, not a chronology or an evolution, as undoubtedly it appeared to my mother if to no-one else. Mediated as memory, it has no linearity. But I can recall playing at Thunder Riders in the playground while they ran as a serial at the Starlight Picturedrome in town, and remember being shocked when a girl in class knew the word 'adjacent', which I had never heard, because she had heard it on a TV advert. Though we still played traditional ring games and sang songs that dated back at least forty years (one was about Charlie Chaplin and the Dardanelles). A rural English childhood of the 1950s was probably largely unchanged for that long: one neighbour remembered hiring fairs, another the first car in Lincolnshire, but they were already in their sixties and seventies. Of course, that still made them moderns. Hoardings, branding, newspapers, postcards, sheet music and photographs would have held no terrors for them. After the model of Geoffrey Pearsall's history of hooliganism, we can push our mediated 'modernity' back to Mopsa in Shakespeare's The Winter's Tale: 'Pray now, buy some: I love a ballad in print' (IV.iv.261), and to Autolycus' store of ribbons and laces. Further back we have Huizinga's (1924) testimony of the European mediaevals' love of high spectacle, high language and high emotion, if we needed more proof than their cathedrals. The quest for the historical moment of primordial experience begins to call us back, as it did Heidegger (for example in the Introduction to Metaphysics, 1961), to the Greeks, especially the pre-Socratics, or else to Homer. Yet both the pre-Socratics and Homer are mediations, since they exist for us only as philological texts. The desire to render an account of pure perception runs everywhere counter to the idea of a perception which remains unmediated. There is a philosophical dilemma here: an unmediated perception can never be communicated, by definition, so there will never be evidence of its occurring except from introspection. That indeed is the route taken by phenomenology, and most of all by Virilio's mentor Merleau-Ponty and by his teacher Husserl: What is needed is not the insistence that one sees with his own eyes; rather it is that he not explain away under the pressure of prejudice what has been seen. Because in the most impressive of the modern sciences, the mathematico-physical, that which is exteriorly the largest part of their work, results from indirect methods, we are only too inclined to overestimate indirect methods and to misunderstand the value of direct comprehensions. However, to the extent that philosophy goes back to ultimate origins, it belongs precisely to its very essence that its scientific work move in spheres of direct intuition (Husserl 1965: 147) It is, as I understand it, that intuition which Virilio stands to defend: the contemplation that occurs in the co-presence of perceiver and perceived which permits the essence of the perceived to enter the perceiver unaltered by theorisation, habit or mediation as the raw material of rational existence. In the late Heidegger, this will become the concept of dwelling, and have a direct engagement with the environment, and with the mode of inhabiting an environment which is both the means and the goal of thought. In Heidegger the nature of that environment is often quite specific: a mountain path, a garden. The confrontation is one between thinker and nature. Philosophy's purpose, as Husserl expresses it, is to strip thought of its prejudices, its accumulated opinions and habits, in order to clarify and purify that primal confrontation. Shakespeare had another take: 'Unaccomodated man is no more but such a poor, bare forked animal as thou art' (Lear III.iv.106-7). I take Shakespeare's part, and pray with Lear for Poor naked wretches, whereso'er you are That bide the pelting of this pitiless storm, How shall your houseless heads and unfed sides, Your looped and windowed raggedness, defend you >From seasons such as these? (III.iv.28-32) 'Unaccomodated': without technologies and bereft of reason, like Lear and Poor Tom on the blasted heath, we are pitiful indeed. In Virilio's Catholic phenomenology, by contrast, the unalienated human is a dream of Adamic innocence, the lost Eden of Milton, without predators, warm, fruitful, attended by angels and conversing with God. The first sign that our first parents had fallen was the technology of clothing and their first punishment agriculture. Yet these form part of our image of innocence today: farming and chaste dress, like the Amish of Peter Weir's Witness, without petrol engines, living a reclaimed tradition of calm, without radios. John Book introduces Rachel, the Amish mother of his child witness, to pop music in a transforming scene at the centre of the narrative, while he in return is introduced to community in the barn-raising sequence. Does perfection lie somewhere between communitarianism and rock 'n' roll? In the remembrance of puberty (rendered innocent in the more recent ideological formations of Hollywood and the music business) perfected in its naturalisation as negation of history? Can this or any such a state of purity exist? Part of the legacy mislaid in the shameful demise of Althusser was the philosophical demolition of the Lukacsian concept of alienation. Where, Althusser demanded, was the unalienated? Where was a worker other than a stranger to her fellows and herself? Where was there primal, self-identical humanity? We might add, if masculinity and femininity are technologies, where lies innocence? In Virilio's thought the answer appears to be: in the moment of pure perception. Drawing on Husserl's attempt to capture the phenomenal moment of intuition as first experience, with a shade of Levinas' (1969) proposal of the face-to-face as first philosophy, Virilio develops his critique of alienated humanity on the basis of immediate perception. We should pause before the etymology of the word; im-mediate, not mediated. In which sense is the politikon zoon capable of that unmediated experience? We would need an immense and detailed history of communication to demonstrate that there is nothing 'natural' about perception, or indeed about such other human attributes as politics, economics, technology, sexuality or communication which have been cited in various philosophical discourses as foundational. More than that, we have no philosophical ground on which to claim that what is presumed to be natural is by that simple token good, either politically, economically, technologically or sexually. Nor, at risk of pure oxymoron, is it possible to imagine a communication that is other than artificial. It is therefore imperative for a theory of alienation to prove that there exists a natural perception, and that it is good. My friend Margaret Marshment proposes the experience of breaking her arm in the bush in Kenya. I can offer a story of my own. I once gashed my hip diving into a waterfall in Northern Quebec among woods where bears were common. Streaming tell-tale blood and limping, I made the mile-long trek back to the road. For a few minutes, probably in shock, life was raw. And I wished for two things: a vehicle and a weapon. Two points emerge. First, that I wanted technologies and that the lack of them shaped my experience. And second, it was a frightening, even terrifying experience that I have no wish to repeat. We have defined the natural by the negative, and in this instance forced a peaceable chap who would no more kill an animal than himself to cast about for a wieldable log with which to assault one. Perhaps this revealed my 'true nature', but it certainly did not reveal an ethical good. Nor are we capable of raw experience. Our perceptions are framed in memories and expectations, both themselves constructed in the horizon not only of our own biographies but of those that have been communicated to us, in fiction as well as fact. I did not expect to pull myself out of the river by my own hair like Baron Munchausen, but I had heard enough about bears both locally and in documentaries and fictions to know that they smell blood from far enough away to make me anxious, and to imagine both my future in ursine intestines, and to plan flight and defence. In short, there is no moment, no perfect Augenblick. Perception takes time. In this I agree with Virilio (1996: 98) who argues in 'L'instant lumière' that a meeting depends on a sufficient duration for mutual apprehension of the parties involved. But I have to disagree with him when he goes on to argue that 'The real time of telecommunications is not only opposed, as we often hear, to the past, to differed (deferred) time, but to the present, its very actuality' (1996: 100). The electronic meeting does indeed take place, and indeed takes time. Though its time may be condensed or telescoped in compression algorithms, it is always unfolded again in its decoding. In fact, those translational processes are necessitated by all communication because all communication is mediated. Perception is already an act of communication, despite the individualist credos of cognitive science. Stereoscopic vision, for example, is limited by the narrowness of the gap between an individual pair of eyes: true stereoscopy is available only to the socius, to the primal band of hunters triangulating the position of prey and danger. That truth which Husserl understands as the goal of both naturalistic science and of phenomenological philosophy as rigorous science is unavailable to the individual: it can only be triangulated by the social in the communicative form of agreement. Moreover, perception takes time because it is always already mediated in consciousness which in turn is always already social and therefore by definition a product not of perception but of communication. If it is the case that consciousness therefore is dependent on communication, raw perception is unavailable to consciousness. Unmediated perception is thus unconscious perception, both in the Lacanian sense that it is not symbolised, and in the sense of someone deprived of consciousness. This, of course, is the mental state Virilio (1991) identifies as picnolepsia , and describes as a distinctive form of absence proper to the contemporary world, typical of motorways and air travel. His observation is good, but his argument incorrect: driving on automatic pilot is a flight from the historical present into the ahistorical, the pure perceptual bliss of the driver at one with the environment. Picnolepsia is an example of pure perception when that perception is not only erased from consciousness but both lethal and suicidal. That it is natural is no defence against its danger. A second, highly specific atemporal phenomenon is constructed in contemporary communications, in some very particular modes of special effect in Hollywood cinema, especially scenes of destruction (Cubitt 1999). But they function in relation to multiple temporalities tugging on the spectator, from the real time of viewing to the narrational time of the film by way of the diegetic clock among many others. To assert the eradication of time in transmission is to elide the quite opposite case which actually obtains: that time has become a raw material for cultural production at the turn of the 21st century. What the signifier was to the art and culture of 1900, the temporalities of communication are to those of 2000. >From gameplay to hypertext novels, from The Matrix to the Aphex Twin, time is at once the central material and the central theme of contemporary communicational research and entertainment. It is so, in fact, precisely because of the globalised communication structure that enables and has been colonised by finance capital. It is no longer the case that time is money, a motto of the productivist era. Today, money is time, and the culture of the 21st century is irrevocably entangled in that relation. To define telecommunication as that which has no present is to deny us the possibility of working in it, for the present is the only time we have in which to make history. When he writes that after cybernetisation, 'the phenomena that happen here in common space no longer happen now in common time, but in an outside-time (outre-temps) over which no-one has any power (1996: 180), Virilio appears as an apologist for precisely the ideological effect sought in the kind of special effect mentioned above: the removal of history-making to a timeless zone situated permanently in a moment unbridgeably to one side of history. Virilio has the vices of a sociologist. He believes that it is possible to make statements about media at large, while the discipline of media studies remains adamant that viewers do not watch 'television' but navigate specific flows; that we do not surf the web but explore specific routes across the network, emphasising the particularity of each instance of each medium, each media production and circulation, and each specific and material navigation of the media culture in the material and specific present. Virilio's second sociological vice is to believe that society, as concept and as essence, antedates communication, which it subordinates to itself. The social cannot determine the communicative, because they are one and the same thing. I go further. As consciousness is a specific effect of the specificity of its society, so the given and specific form of any actually existing society is a function of its communication. In claiming that communication forms societies I do not want to defend technological determinism. Technologies are clearly social, and to that extent they too are formations of communication. Rather, I want to argue that attention to the dominant and subordinate modes of communication in any specific historical conjuncture provides us with insight into the structuring constraints on any historically given social formation. To jump to the chase, in the contemporary world, finance capital is the dominant mode of communication. Residual forms such as land-based cultures and 'alienated labour', and emergent forms like diasporan cultural networks, shape the global-local interface in which specific crises emerge: communalism in Bombay, aboriginal rights in Sydney, land reform and indigenous rights in Chiapas, nationalism in Kosovo. Without understanding these communicative ecologies, the specificity of millennarial nationalism, the new Islam and substance abuse among indigenous peoples remains only desperate and insoluble problems. We are not natural. We are human. Our perception is artifice, because it is always already mediated by our ongoing communicative evolution. The point is not to deny what we have become, but to see that it is constructed, and therefore to seize the hour and change the communicative structuring that forms us. One of Virilio's targets is transmission, the sending across that deletes the Levinasian, ethical face-to-face. This is an apt description of finance capital. But it does not describe the critical emergent form of diasporan networks, which function by translation, literally 'bringing across', recognising the malleable materiality of mediation, making of it the raw material of a remade sociality and thus of a new consciousness. Virilio takes the past rather than the future as the measure of the falling off of human communication from a human-scaled geo-temporal reality of the face-to-face. The theses of temporalities as raw material for cultural production and of diasporan networks as emergent communicative form suggest a contrary perspective: that human communication does not yet exist (where the phrase not-yet should evoke the contentless utopianism of Ernst Bloch). In pursuit of this distinction, which I take to be an ethical as well as an aesthetic one, we need to understand the relation between human and animal communication. Human communication is the same as animal communication as long as it is one-to-one or one-to-many. But human communication differs from animal to the extent that it is many-to-many. To this extent Habermas is right, and even McLuhan. But it would be incorrect to say either that this is a natural state of affairs, or that because it is natural it is therefore good. If we are closer to nature in one-to-one communication, to the extent that it is characteristic of animal as well as human communication, nonetheless we do not thereby approach more closely to nature. In fact, the more intensively we communicate face-to-face, the more complexity enters the communication, with subtle interpretations of the most marginal signs, the most fretful analysis of body language and codes of dress, and the finest attention to the nicest points of vocabulary and intonation. By the same token, we approximate the territorial calls of birds or the transmission of directions among the bees in such clearly cultural, historical, and artificial acts as political speeches or broadcasting, even the one-to-many forms of printed novels and poetry. We cannot therefore pretend to descry in either one-to-one or one-to-many communication an equivalence of human and natural communication. If however, we want to argue that many-to-many communication constitutes the grounds of a specifically human nature, we have to be wary of certain distinctions among modes of many-to-many. It might be argued that highly mediated forms like advertising campaigns and blockbuster movies are not singly authored, and therefore fall into the category of many-to-many just as truly as the ideal café society of Habermas' (1989) public sphere, or the polylogue of McLuhan's (1989) global village. Both types -- centre-out group-authored and democratic communications -- are, according to the initial statement, more exclusively human than one-to-one or one-to-many models. But they cannot therefore be argued to be proper to 'human nature' since they are dependent on specific historical conditions for their realisation. They approximate in this to Giedion's (1948) 'anonymous history', sharing with technologies like knitting and baking an open evolution unconstrained by patent or copyright. It may appear that this freedom from legal constraint is a mode of natural evolution, but the law itself is an example of anonymous history, even in those societies in which a constitution has been specifically authored, since jurisprudence elaborates a filigree of arguments, decisions, precedents and cases as a palimpsest over the bare bones of the originating constitutional document. Moreover, the distinction between the two forms of many-to-many communications opens certain key cultural practices to analysis. The centre-out model can be parsed as a group-to-many communication where the group is restricted in membership while the ideal models of Habermas and McLuhan are not. Group-to-many communications typically take the form of more or less stable texts: hoardings, films, newspapers, television channels, computer games. Multiple exemplars resemble one another closely both formally and thematically (I accept Usai's [1994] argument that no two prints of a film are identical: by analogy, no two television receivers display identical image or sound qualities). Such texts exhibit both geographical and temporal stability, and are unaltered as mediations by interpretations, however varied. Many-to-many communications, by contrast, tend to ephemerality and instability, and are easily and typically altered in the process of interpretation. Unlike a film, the 'text' of a dialogue is an evolving fabric. Even where the dialogue is mediated by technologies like e-mail and IRC, each contribution is unstable, like a move in chess, a challenge awaiting a response, incomplete in itself. In other words, even where communications are delayed, as in exchanges of letters, many-to-many polylogues are swifter than group-to-society monologues, with the sole exception of news coverage, which can be seen, in certain moments such as coverage of demonstrations, as a use of the group as a medium for many-to-many communication. Exceptionally, group cultural forms can take on the speed and effervescence of polylogue, notably in improvised performance in dance, drama and music. Group improvisation is a limit case of the group/polylogue distinction. In certain instances -- the Jerry Springer Show for example -- we can descry coded improvisation of the kind attacked by Adorno in his work on jazz, but one which reveals importantly that irrationalism is not excluded from dominant and dominating communications, but rather is amalgamated into it as a non-dialectical binarism resolved in the figure of the master of ceremonies. This co-optation of improvisation into the regulated repetition of narratemes and elements of behaviour is integral to the production of difference as a project of dominance in contemporary society. Like microcuisines, TV talkshow microcultures are as integral to processes of globalisation as the form of the nation-state constituted as nationalism or localism. We are now ready to return to Virilio, via Clausewitz (1968), for whom war is the continuation of policy by other means. Policy in this instance is international, and as such a form of group-to-group communication, in which both groups have restricted memberships. Virilio's argument is that war as communication is foreclosed by the transfer of strategic decision-making from human agents to computers. To this extent, the group-to-group communication is negated by the emergence of non-human communicative agents. My contention is that group-to-group communication is not human. In the first instance, group-to-group is a characteristic of the territorial disputes of primates. But where these standoffs between troops are often conducted as ceremonial, in the sense that physical violence is only part of a bravura display of behaviours, the confrontation between armies ceased to be a communicative and ceremonial event in the Middle Ages with the arrival of the stirrup and even more so with the impersonality of the fortified city. Modern war, dating from this period, is then precisely a negation of communication. Nationalisms as such continue this tradition of non-communication, using both military and, of course in the age of finance capital, economic blockades in place of interaction. We would need to depend upon a Hegelian master-slave dialectic in order to produce a communicative model, and although Clausewitz could, late in the 19th century, still express the argument of policy as communicative, that era is long since gone, as both Virilio and Baudrillard have argued of both the Cold War and the Gulf War. The famous arrogance of Thatcher's foreign policy in the era of the Malvinas War is a further example of this refusal to communicate as the basis of contemporary policy. Group-to-group communication is then in general incommunicative, save only insofar as it can be understood as a function of endocolonisation, that is, as a function of the internal communicative strategy of the group, itself either group-to-many or one-to-many, depending on the precise configuration of the troop. In the instance of recent wars, the cult of the personality as a key propaganda tool both in constructing nationhood and in constructing the enemy ('Saddam') suggest that authoritarianism is integral to group-to-group communication. In the case of heavily targeted TV programming, such as The Jerry Springer Show, the programme design is equally group-to-group. Warring factions on stage are confronted with normative factions in the studio audience, with Springer as the authoritarian representative of the network whose communicative monopoly is thereby ensured. In this instance, the function of the process is to elaborate risks against which that authority can be tested, and to provide closures in which it is reasserted. In other words, the programme exists to ensure that nothing changes. This, I would argue, is precisely the opposite of any workable definition of communication, which is characterised by change. To this extent we must concur with Virilio, that communication as a human attribute is not realised in contemporary global society. On the one hand, producers and consumers have never been so globally and so deeply mutually involved. But on the other, they stand in the most limited and constrained relationships with one another it is possible to imagine, a binary code of consumer market choices: 'Buy me', 'Yes' and 'Buy me', 'No', 'Pay me', 'Yes', 'Pay me', 'No'. But where Virilio argues for a rearward glance at a lost plenum of communication in the Edenic fullness of pre-technological society, we must realise that we are no longer alone. Nature has not left us. Rather the concept of an innocent and extra-human nature stands revealed as a discursive construct, and one that no longer convinces in an ecological era. Moreover, the evolution of human communication is identical with the evolution of human communicative technologies, since all communication is mediation. That these communicative mediations have been turned towards the purposes of the aggregation of wealth, power and reproductive precedence in the hands of a decreasingly small group should teach us the non-natural and inhuman nature of the histories of communication. Indeed. But they should also teach us that, since there is nothing natural about communication, neither is there anything given about it. Dominance. like modern war, is not only incommunicative but anti-communicative. Therefore any history of dominance, such as Virilio's, must emphasise the blockage to communication that it establishes. The order of difference produced in the institution of the nation-state (considered as a function of imperialism and de-colonisation under conditions of globalisation) is just such a blockage. Its impedence can be measured as the difference between the ease of transit of capital and the ease of transit of labour. The nationalism of the United Kingdom has produced, for example, strict and, in the last few days, deadly laws regulating human traffic, while at the same time making itself increasingly transparent to 24-hour global share trading. However there is no such thing as a closed system, whence the failure of the Second Law of Thermodynamics to obtain in either ecosystems or communication systems. Outside the laboratory, all systems are permeable, and because permeable mutable. The struggle for homeostasis against the negentropy of mutation -- carried out in discourses of plague, disease and virus in the press -- is doomed to failure, and doubly so since the very struggle against mutation in the state's immune system induces mutations in that system in order to fight off or neutralise what it perceives as threats to its integrity and discretion. As a result the integral and discrete is forced to become an evolving organism, generating new modes of internal communication in the act of seeking to control and minimise communication with what lies beyond the boundaries through whose difference it wishes to establish its integrity. Ecological theme run through Virilio's work from Popular Defense and Ecological Struggles (1990) to the final pages of Cybermonde: la politique du pire (1996). There is an illuminating comparison to be made between Baudrillard, who finds deserts so facsinating because you are delivered from all depth there -- a brilliant, mobile, superficial neutrality, a challenge to meaning and profundity, a challenge to nature and culture, an outer hyperspace, with no origin, no reference-points (Baudrillard 1998: 124) and Virilio, for whom the desert resembles the sea. It gives the feeling of our presence on a planet. I love a landscape where one feels the planet, where the territorial body of the planet Earth is perceptible at a reduced scale. I love the local when it reveals the global, and the global when one can poerceive it starting from the local. One should not lose either, but hold the two together (1996: 108) Virilio's anti-nihilistic recognition of planetary being is an inspiration for this critique, for it suggests the kinds of mutuality required if we are to recognise ourselves as global citizens. But his generous understanding of the non-human has to be rewritten, away from a nature defined by its difference from culture and its externality to the human and technological. We can no longer argue with Virilio that history is a landscape of events: we know that a landscape is an event in history. An ecology is not an entity distinct from us, laid out as map or depiction, but a fruit of technical actions upon it (including the now deliberate act of leaving it as wilderness). And the landscape is an event that feeds back at both physiological and psychological levels, warming and cooling, feeding or starving, welcoming or forbidding our passage across it. By this same token, the landscape as history, as end-product and as ground of action, since it cannot be defined as exclusive of the human, cannot be defined as wholly organic. For at least the seven thousand years for which we have evidence of trading across the rivers and oceans of the Old World, we have been symbiotes with our technologies, and especially with our communications technologies. Under conditions of global finance capital, information wants to be paid for, but communication still seeks to be free. The attempt to monopolise communication which underlies the phenomena which Virilio is most intensely engaged with is doomed to fail, since the concept of monopoly excludes an other with whom to communicate. More particularly, Virilio misreads the omens when he characterises communications technologies as alien others to whom the powers of communication have been delegated. The attempt to monopolise communication has produced that massive and capital-intensive infrastructure of satellites and telecommunication which, perversely, has enabled a new form of communication. In the first great historicisation of our species, agriculture opened up channels of communication between the human and organic phyla. The second, which we can characterise as the ongoing industrial revolution, the revolution of the modern which accelerates from the age of the stirrup and the water wheel, instigates communication between the human and machinic phyla. Perhaps, like primaeval Deleuzes and Guattaris, the nomadic hunter-gatherers looked at the first sedentary farmers with just such an apocalyptic intuition of the end of true humanity as Virilio derives from the intensifying relationships we establish with each other through the increasingly demanding mediations of our machines. Virilio's forebodings are inaccurate, but only because he is properly fearful of the tendency of dominance in contemporary communication toward the monopoly structure of transmission. In this perspective the present is indeed in danger as the ground of history-making. The new cultural interest in time as raw material, however, is an instance of the permeability of the system. The focus on time urges a concentration on the medium as transport, as a work of carriage across spaces and times. While the defensive conservatism of the discrete seeks to ring-fence privacy, national sovereignty and, indeed, the immaculate perception which Virilio wishes to preserve, the emergence of diasporan networks as a counter-model for planetary communication proposes not the preservation but the translation of data. The fluid, indeterminate, indiscrete and maculate translations of diasporan nets evolve only as a consequence and in the form of communication, in creative partnership with the media they foreground. Our technologies are as integral to that evolving communication as our animal bodies, and as hard-wired to the world. That they mediate, and do so at the speed of light, should encourage us with the thought that the present is a determinate temporality governed by the universal constant. That present is not innocent, but neither is it wholly determined. Nothing is forgotten in the millenia-old conversations of humankind, least of all the past vagaries of communication itself that become properties of its latest form. Such memories and histories exist in multiple modalities in the present: as the pattern of fibre-optic cables laid along the ancient paths of trade winds and caravanserai, as the remnants of ancient religion in verbal greetings and imprecations, perhaps even in a Lamarckian patterning of dendrites to produce the Chomskyan 'language instinct'. But despite Virilio's fears, the present is not the already achieved and completed moment that the myth of instantaneous communication pretends to, bringing us 'live' pictures carrying the message that whatever is depicted is already over. Considered not as given but as raw material, the present becomes the workshop in which the future is produced, the ephemeral and to that extent the beautiful and ethical moment in which the teleological imagination of the end of history and the end of dialogue stands to be proved to be no more than an optical illusion. That proof is the anti-teleological but wholly eschatological action of future making, based in the evolutionary mutations of translation, the work of interpretation and conversation which is both the vehicle and the outcome of a human ecology. Our present, as history, is that in which the organic and the technological can for the first time be seen not as opposites, nor as equally alien to the human, but as intrinsic to the evolution of the future in the communications of the present. Virilio's jeremiads are still invaluable reminders of the urgency of this historical juncture, of the cost if we should lose communication and be shuffled into homeostatic monopoly. There can be no question of preserving the present as an unchanged and unchanging instance of the face-to-face: the present is not a plenum but a process. To idealise the immediate excludes the possibility of the instability and failure of dominance to dominate. Far from excluding technologies, we should embrace them, with all due caution and alert to the purposes that have designed the specific devices we have in front of us, ready to aid in their evolution as the price of ensuring our own. To keep the present as process, and to evolve, we will need all the allies we can get, organic and mechanical. REFERENCES Baudrillard, Jean (1988c), America, trans Chris Turner (Material Word), Verso, London. Clausewitz, Carl von (1968), On War, Penguin, Harmondsworth. Cubitt, Sean (1999), 'Introduction. Le réel c'est l'impossible: The Sublime Time of Special Effects' in Screen v. 40 n.2, Summer, 123-30. Giedion, Siegfried (1948), Mechanisation Takes Command: A Contribution to Anonymous History, Norton, New York. Habermas, Jürgen (1989 [1962]), The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Enquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society, trans Thomas Burger with the assistance of Frederick Lawrence, Polity, Cambridge. Heidegger, Martin (1961), An Introduction to Metaphysics, trans Ralph Manheim, Anchor Doubleday, New York. Huizinga, Johan (1924), The Waning of the Middle Ages: A Study of the Forms of Life, Thought and Art in France and the Netherlands in the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Centuries, trans. F. Hopman, Penguin, Harmondsworth. Husserl, Edmund (1965), Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy, trans Quentin Lauer, Harper & Row, New York. Levinas, Emmanuel (1969), Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, tr Alphonso Lingis, Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh. McLuhan, Marshall and Bruce R Powers (1989), The Global Village: Transformations in World Life and Media in the 21st Century, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Usai, Paolo Cherchi (1994), Burning Passions: An Introduction to the Study of Silent Cinema, trans Emma Sansone Rittle, BFI, London. Virilio, Paul (1990), Popular Defense and Ecological Struggles, trans Mark Polizzotti, Semiotext(e), New York. Virilio, Paul (1991), The Aesthetics of Disappearance, trans Philip Beitchman, Semiotext(e), New York. Virilio, Paul (1996), Un paysage d'événements, Galilée, Paris. Virilio, Paul (1998a), Cybermonde: la politique du pire, entretien avec Phillippe Petit, textuel/Seuil, Paris. # distributed via <nettime>: no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a moderated mailing list for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@bbs.thing.net and "info nettime-l" in the msg body # archive: http://www.nettime.org contact: nettime@bbs.thing.net