Nmherman on Sat, 27 Apr 2002 20:05:01 +0200 (CEST) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
[Nettime-bold] Juvenilia Ante Academia 4/4 |
In my second discussion starter, I continued this line of reasoning in discussing Part Three of Right to Literacy. In these essays, I felt there to be a significant thematic thread in which the effect of literacy on cognition was examined much in the same way that Vygotsky and Whorf took it up. I focused particularly on Beth Daniell's statement that "according to [Frederick] Engels, human beings use labor and tools to change nature, and in doing so, change themselves" (RTL 202). Here we see a definite case of an instrumental paradigm; the analogy is even made between language and "tools" (such as our example of the hammer). While most of the essayists in this section reject the idea of the "Great Leap" theories of Ong and others, in which human development reaches a watershed with the onset of alphabetic literacy, they nonetheless retain the idea that language-use significantly shapes people's cognition. The idea that literate practices are not "decontextualized" as Ong claims is reflected in the essays by Keith Walters and Deborah Brandt, in which they argue that literate practices are always profoundly social in operation. Charles Schuster advocates a highly communication-based critique of instrumental literacy when he writes of "the illiterate" that "they have been denied genuine listeners" (RTL 229), and that all human language "exists in an interactive medium" (RTL 229). Clearly, these essays by Brandt, Daniell, Walters, and Schuster make a strong move toward limiting the separated and individual definition of how language-abilities form and operate. This is clearly, from the point of view of interrogating instrumental concepts, a step forward. However, one serious caveat needs to be noted. As Daniell suggested in her quote of Engels, the idea that language-practice is always social in nature does not necessarily preclude the kind of instrumentalism that Whorf proposed. The idea that literate practices are always social in context and never "decontextualized" and solitary needs to be augmented by an accompanying assertion that there is a communicative or relationship-based aspect of human language which is necessary due to the interactive nature of multi-subject discourse, and perhaps even programmed into each human brain by genetic heredity. It is useful to reject Ong's assertion of a "Great Leap" to individual awareness, but if the rejection does not include a decisive statement that social community and/or human genetic nature--and not merely social convention--necessitates an interactive practice, then the effort to curtail and limit instrumentalization has only been partially completed. It is indispensable to any definition of human language-practice as an "end" in itself and not a "means only" that some recognition be made of an internal and innate human language faculty; without such a recognition it is impossible ever to argue that a person's linguistic rights and nature have been denied or distorted. Once the tension and conflict between instrumental and communicative paradigms of language-practice has been accepted as a line of inquiry, two concepts--myth and taboo--become extremely useful in placing this opposition in a larger context. These terms may seem to be at first somewhat alien to the discipline of literacy studies, and rather incommensurable with the ideas of instrumentality and communication, but this is only a surface incongruence. In fact, myth and taboo are the most ancient principles by which the struggle between instrumental and communicative concepts of literate practice has been negotiated. If we accept the argument that human language is not a "means only," but an innate faculty which all normally developing humans possess a full awareness of and facility with, then it must follow that any attempt to impose a system which instrumentalizes language must do so in the face of a strong and intuitive resistance by those on whom such a system would be imposed. People's direct knowledge must be suppressed; they must be made to feel alienated from meaning in language and able to re-access it only through the wholesale reliance on the imposed system. If we understand instrumentalization as a denial of certain innate human attributes, clearly any theoretical model which justifies such a denial must be grounded in an extra-experiential sphere, untestable through direct sources of evidence. Any such model would fall under the category of myth: in the American Heritage Dictionary, "myth" can mean "A notion based more on tradition or convenience than on fact; a received idea." The concept of taboo complements that of myth, and makes the opposition between communication and instrumentality even clearer. If myth carries out the denial of aspects of human language-nature by severing the theoretical plane from the experiential, taboo reinforces and implements this severance by making obedience to myth the condition of social acceptance. In other words, in order to suppress or distort communicative principles, it is most effective to make access to even the diminished level of communicative agency dependent on an acceptance of that diminished status. In this way, taboo uses the threat of total ostracism to enforce wider allegiance to a partial reduction of social empowerment, that is, to a partial ostracism. Clearly, the interconnections between instrumental/mythic constructions and taboo-based, anti-communicative discourse norms are rigorous and compelling, but not always readily discernable by methodologies which already possess an internalization of the myth-driven forms of discourse-control. _______________________________________________ Nettime-bold mailing list Nettime-bold@nettime.org http://amsterdam.nettime.org/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/nettime-bold